PHIL20490 Knowledge & Scepticism

Academic Year 2024/2025

"A common refrain heard around New Scientist‘s offices in recent weeks has been “episte… what?!” Even among educated and well-informed people, epistemology – the study of knowledge – is neither a familiar word nor a well-known field of enquiry. But it has never been more important." [New Scientist Editorial, 29 March 2017]

This course provides an introduction to epistemology: the study of knowledge (the name 'epistemology comes from the Greek words 'epistēmē', meaning 'knowledge', and 'logos', meaning 'science or study of'). Epistemology has always been one of the central - if not *the* central -- areas of philosophy, and it has a great deal of relevance both theoretically and practically. The purpose of the course is to help you to understand some of the core questions and theories of epistemology, and to help you to think about the questions for yourself so you can form your own independent views about them.

Why is epistemology so important? Because knowledge is generally seen the primary goal of inquiry, whether in ordinary life (I want to *know* when the bus will arrive) or in any area of expertise (I want the doctor to *know* what's wrong with me, and the mechanic to *know* how to fix my car). But what exactly do want when we want to know something, or when we want someone else to know something? What's the difference between knowing something, and just having an opinion about it? (The difference matters: I hope the surgeon *knows* how to do the operation, rather than just having an opinion about it!) Does knowing something require believing it? Can you know something that's not true? In other words, what exactly *is* knowledge?

Philosophers have been especially interested in the question of what knowledge is, because if we can answer that question, we can start to answer another important question: what can we really know? What sort of knowledge is possible? For example, many philosophers throughout history have argued that we can't know what the objects outside our own minds are *really* like; they argue that we can only really know how things outside our minds *seem* to us, or how they impact on our senses. According to these philosophers, our knowledge of the world outside our minds never really extends beyond our own sensations. This idea -- that we are, to some extent, trapped in our own sensations -- has been a recurring theme not only in philosophy in both the East and West, but in different global religions and in science fiction.

The philosophical view that we can't know anything (or anything much) about the world outside our own sensations is called 'philosophical scepticism'. But even if we reject philosophical scepticism, there are questions about knowledge we still have to answer. For example, there are questions about the different *sources* of knowledge. Is perception is a source of knowledge, and if so, how? Is memory a source of knowledge, and if so, how? Is reason by itself a source of knowledge, and if so, how? And there are questions about how we can know certain kinds of things. For example, how do we know what's morally right and wrong? How do we know what's possible and impossible? How do we know about the future? Epistemologists address these questions, and more.

There is also an important connection between knowledge and evidence. It's natural to think that in order to know something, we have to have reasons for believing it -- in other words, we need to have some *evidence* in support of our belief. But how strong does our evidence have to be to give us knowledge? Can someone know something without having *any* evidence for it? Do we need reasons for accepting our evidence -- in other words, do we need evidence for our evidence? What form does evidence have to take? For example, do we have to be able to reflect on our evidence in order to have knowledge? Can a group of people know something based on 'shared' evidence? Can babies and animals have knowledge, and if so, what does that tell us about the relationship between knowledge and evidence, or about the nature of evidence?

Many of the traditional questions and theories of epistemology are focussed on knowledge from a largely theoretical perspective. But recently there has been a much greater (and welcome) focus in epistemology on the *social* and *ethical* dimensions of knowledge. For example, the philosopher Miranda Fricker argues in her 2007 book *Epistemic Injustice* that there is a specific kind of injustice that involves holding certain people to higher standards of evidence because of their social identity (for example, as having a certain gender or ethnic identity). Others have argued that whether we should believe something doesn't just depend on whether it is rational to do so, but whether believing it would contribute to social structures of injustice. In both cases, questions of knowledge are connected with ethical questions concerning injustice and oppression. And epistemology also has a political dimension. For example, what exactly do people mean when we say that 'conspiracy theories', 'fake news', and 'epistemic bubbles' pose a threat to democracy? What sort of epistemic duties do individual people -- as opposed to e.g. governments and private companies -- have in an environment that contains lots of bad information?

The course is divided into two halves. In the first half, we address some of the traditional questions in epistemology, such as: what is knowledge, and how does it relate to belief? What is the relation between knowledge and evidence? Should we take philosophical scepticism seriously?

In the second part of the course, we address questions concerning the *social* and *ethical* dimensions of knowledge, such as: are there ethical as well as rational standards of belief? How do we gain knowledge from others, and are there forms of injustice specifically connected with the transmission of knowledge? How should we understand concepts like 'conspiracy theories', 'fake news', and 'epistemic bubbles'?

Show/hide contentOpenClose All

Curricular information is subject to change

Learning Outcomes:

If you seriously engage with this course, you'll learn to:

1. Critically reflect on classic and contemporary debates in epistemology.
2. Identify key concepts and theories in epistemology, and show awareness of potential problems that have led to the refinement of those concepts and theories in the course of the relevant debates.
3. Interpret and understand classic and contemporary texts in epistemology.
4. Write well-structured and well-argued philosophical essays that explain and critically assess the key concepts and theories introduced in the module.
5. Respond to constructive feedback on your arguments and views.
6. Articulate your own responses to philosophical views, support them with reasons, and defend them in light of potential objections.

Indicative Module Content:

The module is divided into two halves. In the first half (Weeks 1-7), we'll address questions concerning the nature and scope of knowledge, such as:

1. What is the relationship between knowledge, truth, and belief?
2. Is it possible to provide a strict definition of what it is to *know* something?
3. Does knowledge require *certainty*?
4. Does the *epistemic justification of belief* depend solely on what goes on in our heads, or also on how we relate to the world around us?
5. How should we respond to those who argue that we have no real knowledge of anything outside our own private experiences and sensations?

For an introduction to some of the topics of this half, see here (copy and paste this link into your browser):
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=r_Y3utIeTPg&t=123s

In the second half of the course (Weeks 8-12), we'll address some questions concerning the social and ethical dimensions of knowledge, such as:

6. Do ethical considerations favour a particular view of knowledge?
7. Are there *ethical* as well as rational standards of belief, i.e. can it be wrong to believe something even if it is perfectly rational to believe it?
8. How do we gain knowledge from others, and are there special forms of injustice connected with the transmission of knowledge?
9. How should we understand concepts like 'conspiracy theories', 'fake news', and 'epistemic bubbles'?

For an introduction to some of the topics of this half, see here (copy and paste this link into your browser):
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=p4AybWp4O8Q

Student Effort Hours: 
Student Effort Type Hours
Lectures

24

Tutorial

7

Autonomous Student Learning

94

Total

125

Approaches to Teaching and Learning:
1. TEACHING

This course is taught on the basis of 22 in-person lectures (two one-hour lectures per week for eleven weeks), and 7 one-hour in-person tutorials (delivered by a graduate tutor who is an expert in the area).

Lectures will be delivered in person during timetabled slots, and involve the presentation of content by the lecturer and in-class discussion.

In tutorials, you'll have the opportunity to discuss and debate the week's readings and the content presented in the lectures in detail, as well as to raise questions concerning the material with the graduate tutor.Tutorial attendees will often be divided into smaller groups who will discuss certain questions related to the week's reading and then feed back their answers to the whole group. There will also be an opportunity to discuss essay plans and essay feedback in tutorials. Tutorials will usually be structured around specific questions and readings provided in advance by the tutor or lecturer. 

2. LEARNING

Learning for this module is centred around content presented in lectures, reading material and videos shared on Brightspace, discussion and debate, and essay writing.

You'll be expected to read short set texts in advance of the lectures, to attend lectures, and to actively participate in tutorials. You'll be supported in your learning of the course material by lecturers and tutors, both in lectures and tutorials, by email, and in set office hours. You'll be supported in your essay writing by a lecture on how to write a good philosophical essay, reading materials on how to write a good philosophical essay, comments on a draft essay, clear feedback on submissions by the lecturer and/or tutor, and a rubric accompanying essays. 
Requirements, Exclusions and Recommendations

Not applicable to this module.


Module Requisites and Incompatibles
Incompatibles:
PHIL20290 - Knowledge and Reality


 
Assessment Strategy  
Description Timing Open Book Exam Component Scale Must Pass Component % of Final Grade
Assignment(Including Essay): 1500-word essay. n/a Graded No

35

Participation in Learning Activities: Participation in tutorials. n/a Pass/Fail Grade Scale No

15

Exam (In-person): Written exam. n/a Graded No

50


Carry forward of passed components
Yes
 
Resit In Terminal Exam
Spring No
Please see Student Jargon Buster for more information about remediation types and timing. 
Feedback Strategy/Strategies

• Feedback individually to students, on an activity or draft prior to summative assessment
• Feedback individually to students, post-assessment
• Group/class feedback, post-assessment
• Peer review activities

How will my Feedback be Delivered?

1. The lecturer and tutor will provide feedback on draft essays prior to submission (as long as drafts are presented by an agreed date). 2. The essay will be returned with written feedback. 3. After the essay has been submitted, there will be group/class feedback from the lecturer/tutor. 4. Students will have the opportunity to engage in self-assessment activities before and after essay submission in tutorials.